FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94  
95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   >>   >|  
o is so striking that, if not historically connected, they must at least be regarded as expressions of similar philosophic needs. The Hindu classification to which we specially refer is that of Kanada, who lays down six categories, or classes of existence, a seventh being generally added by the commentators. The term employed is _Padartha_, meaning "signification of a word." This is in entire harmony with the Aristotelian doctrine, the categories of which may with truth be described as significations of simple terms, [Greek: tha katha medemian sueplokhen legomena]. The six categories of Kanada are Substance, Quality, Action, Genus, Individuality, and Concretion or Co-inherence. To these is added Non-Existence, Privation or Negation. _Substance_ is the permanent substance in which _Qualities_ exist. _Action_, belonging to or inhering in substances, is that which produces change, _Genus_ belongs to substance, qualities and actions; there are higher and lower genera. _Individuality_, found only in substance, is that by which a thing is self-existent and marked off from others. _Concretion_ or Co-inherence denotes inseparable or necessary connection, such as that between substance and quality. Under these six classes, [Greek: gene tou hontos], Kanada then proceeds to range the facts of the universe.[1] Greek philosophy Within Greek philosophy itself there were foreshadowings of the Aristotelian doctrine, but nothing so important as to warrant the conclusion that Aristotle was directly influenced by it. Doubtless the One and Many, Being and Non-Being, of the Eleatic dialectic, with their subordinate oppositions, may be called categories, but they are not so in the Aristotelian sense, and have little or nothing in common with the later system. Their starting-point and results are wholly diverse. Nor does it appear necessary to do more than mention the Pythagorean table of principles, the number of which is supposed to have given rise to the decuple arrangement adopted by Aristotle. The two classifications have nothing in common; no term in the one list appears in the other; and there is absolutely nothing in the Pythagorean principles which could have led to the theory of the categories.[2] Plato. One naturally turns to Plato when endeavouring to discover the genesis of any Aristotelian doctrine, and undoubtedly there are in the Pl
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94  
95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
categories
 
Aristotelian
 
substance
 
Kanada
 

doctrine

 

principles

 

Aristotle

 

philosophy

 

Pythagorean

 

Action


inherence

 

Concretion

 

Substance

 

common

 

Individuality

 

classes

 

endeavouring

 
influenced
 
Doubtless
 

discover


dialectic

 

naturally

 
called
 

oppositions

 

directly

 

subordinate

 
Eleatic
 

genesis

 

Within

 
universe

proceeds

 
undoubtedly
 

warrant

 

conclusion

 
important
 

foreshadowings

 

adopted

 

arrangement

 

number

 

supposed


decuple

 
mention
 
diverse
 

wholly

 

absolutely

 

system

 

theory

 

appears

 

starting

 
results