FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96  
97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   >>   >|  
of the _ten_ categories, does not stand or fall with only one portion of Aristotle's works. It is surprising that there should yet be so much uncertainty as to the real significance of the categories, and that we should be in nearly complete ignorance as to the process of thought by which, Aristotle was led to the doctrine. On both points It is difficult to extract from the matter before us anything approaching a satisfactory solution. The terms employed to denote the categories have been scrutinized with the utmost care, but they give little help. The most important--[Greek: k. tou ontos] or [Greek: tes ousias, gene tou ontos] or [Greek: ton onton, gene] simply, [Greek: tha prota] or [Greek: tha koina prota, ai ptoseis], or [Greek: ai diaireseis]--only indicate that the categories are general classes into which Being as such may be divided, that they are _summa genera_. The expressions [Greek: gene ton kategorion] and [Greek: schemata ton k.], which are used frequently, seem to lead to another and somewhat different view. [Greek: kategoria] being taken to mean that which is predicated, [Greek: gene ton k.] would signify the most general classes of predicates, the framework into the divisions of which all predicates must come. To this interpretation there are objections. The categories must be carefully distinguished from predicables; in the scholastic phraseology the former refer to _first intentions_, the latter to _second intentions_, i.e. the one denote real, the other logical connexion. Further, the categories cannot without careful explanation be defined as predicates; they are this and something more. The most important category, [Greek: ousia], in one of its aspects cannot be predicate at all. In the [Greek: Kategoriai] Aristotle prefixes to his enumeration a grammatico-logical disquisition on homonyms and synonyms, and on the elements of the proposition, i.e. subject and predicate. He draws attention to the fact that things are spoken of either in the connexion known as the proposition, e.g. "a man runs," or apart from such connexion, e.g. "man" and "runs." He then proceeds, "Of things spoken of apart from their connexion in a proposition ([Greek: ton katha medemian sumplokhen legomenon]), each signifies either Substance ([Greek: ousia]), or Quantity ([Greek: poson]), or Quality ([Greek: poion]), or Relation ([Greek: pros ti],) or Where
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96  
97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
categories
 
connexion
 
proposition
 
predicates
 

Aristotle

 

predicate

 

denote

 

important

 

logical

 

intentions


general

 

classes

 

things

 

spoken

 

Further

 

Quality

 

Quantity

 
Substance
 
phraseology
 

scholastic


predicables

 

carefully

 
distinguished
 

careful

 

objections

 

Relation

 
interpretation
 

enumeration

 

grammatico

 
prefixes

Kategoriai

 
disquisition
 

subject

 

elements

 
homonyms
 

synonyms

 

aspects

 

legomenon

 

attention

 

defined


signifies

 
category
 
sumplokhen
 

proceeds

 

medemian

 

explanation

 

genera

 

points

 

difficult

 
extract