FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107  
108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   >>   >|  
l presented, "as a substitute for the abortive classification of Existences, termed the categories of Aristotle," the following as an enumeration of all nameable things:--(1) Feelings, or states of consciousness; (2) The minds which experience these feelings; (3) Bodies, or external objects which excite certain of those feelings; (4) Successions and co-existences, likenesses and unlikenesses, between feelings or states of consciousness.[14] This classification proceeds on a quite peculiar view of the categories, and is here presented only for the sake of completeness. Modern psychologists. By modern psychologists the subject has been closely investigated. Professor G.F. Stout (_Manual of Psychology_, vol. ii. pp. 312 foll.) defines categories as "forms of cognitive consciousness, universal principles or relations presupposed either in all cognition or in all cognition of a certain kind." He then treats External (or Physical) Reality, Space, Time, Causality and "Thinghood" from the standpoint of the perceptual consciousness; showing in what sense the categories of causality, substance and the rest exist in the sphere of perception. As contrasted with the ideational, the perceptual consciousness is concerned with practice. Perception tells the child of things as separate entities, not in their ultimate relations as parts of a coherent whole. G.T. Ladd (_Psychology Descriptive and Explanatory_, ch. xxi., on "Space, Time and Causality") defines the categories from the psychological standpoint as "those highly abstract conceptions which the mind frames by reflection upon its own most general modes of behaviour. They are our own notions resulting from co-operation of imagination and judgment, concerning the ultimate and unanalyzable forms of our own existence and development." In other words, the categories are highly abstract, have no content, and are realized as a kind of thinking which has for its object all the other mental processes. AUTHORITIES.--Besides those quoted above, see Eduard v. Hartmann, _Kategorienlehre_ (Leipzig, 1896), and "Begriff der Kategorialfunktion", in _Zeitschr. f. Philos. und phil. Krit._ cxv. (1899), pp. 9-19; E. Konig in the same periodical cxiii. (1889), pp. 232-279, and cxiv. (1899), pp. 78-105; F.A. Trendelenburg, _Geschichte der Kategorienlehre_ (1846); P. Ragnisco _Storia critica delle categorie_ (2 vols.,
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107  
108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

categories

 

consciousness

 
feelings
 

psychologists

 
standpoint
 

perceptual

 

ultimate

 

Causality

 

cognition

 

highly


states

 
Psychology
 

relations

 

abstract

 
things
 
defines
 
classification
 

Kategorienlehre

 

presented

 
existence

development
 

unanalyzable

 

conceptions

 

frames

 
psychological
 
Descriptive
 

Explanatory

 

reflection

 

notions

 

resulting


operation
 

imagination

 

content

 

behaviour

 

general

 

judgment

 

Eduard

 

periodical

 

critica

 
categorie

Storia

 
Ragnisco
 
Trendelenburg
 

Geschichte

 

quoted

 
Besides
 

AUTHORITIES

 
thinking
 

object

 
mental