FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139   140   141   142   143   144   145   146   147  
148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164   165   166   167   168   169   170   171   172   >>   >|  
S: 1. S in M, but not in P; 2. S in the overlap of M and P; 3. S in M, some S in P. ] Again, unless the Minor Premiss is affirmative, no matter what the Major Premiss may be, you can draw no conclusion. For if the Minor Premiss is negative, all that you know is that All S or Some S lies somewhere outside M; and however M may be situated relatively to P, that knowledge cannot help towards knowing how S lies relatively to P. All S may be P, or none of it, or part of it. Given all M is in P; the All S (or Some S) which we know to be outside of M may lie anywhere in P or out of it. [Illustration: Concentric circles of P and M, M in center, with 5 instances of circle of S: 1. S wholly outside P and M; 2. S partly overlapping both P and M, and partly outside both; 3. S overlapping P, but outside M; 4. S wholly within P, but wholly outside M; 5. S touching circle of P, but outside both circles. ] Similarly, in the Second Figure, trial and simple inspection of all possible conditions shows that there can be no conclusion unless the Major Premiss is universal, and one of the premisses negative. Another and more common way of eliminating the invalid forms, elaborated in the Middle Ages, is to formulate principles applicable irrespective of Figure, and to rule out of each Figure the moods that do not conform to them. These regulative principles are known as The Canons of the Syllogism. _Canon I._ In every syllogism there should be three, and not more than three, terms, and the terms must be used throughout in the same sense. It sometimes happens, owing to the ambiguity of words, that there seem to be three terms when there are really four. An instance of this is seen in the sophism:-- He who is most hungry eats most. He who eats least is most hungry. [.'.] He who eats least eats most. This Canon, however, though it points to a real danger of error in the application of the syllogism to actual propositions, is superfluous in the consideration of purely formal implication, it being a primary assumption that terms are univocal, and remain constant through any process of inference. Under this Canon, Mark Duncan says (_Inst. Log._, iv. 3, 2), is comprehended another commonly expressed in this form: There should be nothing in the conclusion that was not in the premisses: inasmuch as if there were anything in the conclusion that was in neither of the premisses, there
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139   140   141   142   143   144   145   146   147  
148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164   165   166   167   168   169   170   171   172   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

Premiss

 

conclusion

 
Figure
 

premisses

 

wholly

 

hungry

 

overlapping

 
circles
 

partly

 

principles


syllogism

 

negative

 

circle

 
points
 
ambiguity
 

instance

 

sophism

 
constant
 

comprehended

 

Duncan


commonly
 

expressed

 
inference
 

process

 

superfluous

 

consideration

 

purely

 

propositions

 

actual

 
danger

application

 

formal

 

implication

 
remain
 

univocal

 
primary
 
assumption
 

elaborated

 

Illustration

 
Concentric

center

 
touching
 
Similarly
 

Second

 

instances

 

matter

 

affirmative

 
overlap
 
knowing
 

situated