FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76  
77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   >>   >|  
elves or things in relation to one another; that is, it does not represent any determination of things which would attach to the objects themselves and would remain, even though we abstracted from all subjective conditions of perception. For neither absolute nor relative[56] determinations of objects can be perceived prior to the existence of the things to which they belong, and therefore not _a priori_."[57] It is, of course, implied that in experience, where we do not discover determinations of objects prior to the existence of the objects, we do apprehend determinations of things as they are in themselves, and not as they are in relation to us. Thus we should expect the conclusion to be, not that all that we know is phenomenal--which is Kant's real position--but that spatial (and temporal) relations alone are phenomenal, i. e. that they alone are the result of a transmutation due to the nature of our perceiving faculties.[58] This conclusion would, of course, be absurd, for what Kant considers to be the empirically known qualities of objects disappear, if the spatial character of objects is removed. Moreover, Kant is prevented by his theory of perception from seeing that this is the real solution of his problem, absurd though it may be. Since perception is held to arise through the origination of sensations by things in themselves, empirical knowledge is naturally thought of as knowledge about sensations, and since sensations are palpably within the mind, and are held to be due to things in themselves, knowledge about sensations can be regarded as phenomenal. [56] The first sentence shows that 'relative determinations' means, not 'determinations of objects in relation to us', but 'determinations of objects in relation to one another.' Cf. B. 37, M. 23; and B. 66 fin., 67 init., M. 40 (where these meanings are confused). [57] B. 42, M. 26. [58] This conclusion is also to be expected because, inconsistently with his real view, Kant is here (B. 41-2, M. 25-6) under the influence of the presupposition of our ordinary consciousness that in perception we are confronted by things in themselves, known to be spatial, and not by appearances produced by unknown things in themselves. Cf. (B. 41, M. 25) "and thereby of obtaining immediate representation of them [i. e. objects];" and (B. 42, M. 26) "the receptivity of the subject to be affected by objects necessari
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76  
77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

objects

 

things

 

determinations

 
perception
 
sensations
 

relation

 

spatial

 
conclusion
 

phenomenal

 

knowledge


absurd

 

relative

 

existence

 
subject
 

empirical

 

receptivity

 

representation

 
thought
 

palpably

 
affected

necessari

 
naturally
 

regarded

 

sentence

 
expected
 

presupposition

 

ordinary

 

inconsistently

 

influence

 

consciousness


confronted

 

unknown

 

appearances

 

confused

 
meanings
 

produced

 
obtaining
 
faculties
 
priori
 

belong


perceived

 

implied

 

experience

 
expect
 

apprehend

 

discover

 

absolute

 
determination
 

represent

 
attach