FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106  
107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   >>   >|  
ster," "servant," since we can say either "the master of the servant," or "the servant of the master". In mediaeval logic the term _Relata_ was confined to these perfect cases, but the Category had a wider scope with Aristotle. And he expressly raised the question whether a word might not have as much right to be put in another Category as in this. Indeed, he went further than his critics in his suggestions of what Relation might be made to include. Thus: "big" signifies Quality; yet a thing is big with reference to something else, and is so far a Relative. Knowledge must be knowledge of something, and is a relative: why then should we put "knowing" (_i.e._, learned) in the Category of Quality. "Hope" is a relative, as being the hope _of_ a man and the hope of something. Yet we say, "I have hope," and there hope would be in the category of Having, Appurtenance. For the solution of all such difficulties, Aristotle falls back upon the forms of common speech, and decides the place of words in his categories according to them. This was hardly consistent with his proposal to deal with separate words out of syntax, if by this was meant anything more than dealing with them without reference to truth or falsehood. He did not and could not succeed in dealing with separate words otherwise than as parts of sentences, owing their signification to their position as parts of a transient plexus of thought. In so far as words have their being in common speech, and it is their being in this sense that Aristotle considers in the Categories, it is a transient being. What being they represent besides is, in the words of Porphyry, a very deep affair, and one that needs other and greater investigation. [Footnote 1: [Greek: ton kata medemian symploken legomenon hekaston etoi ousian semainei, e poson, e poion, e pros ti, e pou, e pote, e keisthai, e echein, e poiein, e paschein.] (Categ. ii. 5.)] [Footnote 2: To describe the Categories as a grammatical division, as Mansel does in his instructive Appendix C to Aldrich, is a little misleading without a qualification. They are non-logical inasmuch as they have no bearing on any logical purpose. But they are grammatical only in so far as they are concerned with words. They are not grammatical in the sense of being concerned with the function of words in predication. The unit of grammar in this sense is the sentence, a combination of words in
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106  
107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

servant

 

Aristotle

 
grammatical
 

Category

 

Footnote

 

Categories

 

concerned

 
relative
 

reference

 

master


common

 

speech

 

Quality

 
separate
 
dealing
 

logical

 

transient

 
affair
 

symploken

 

legomenon


medemian
 

investigation

 
greater
 

position

 

plexus

 

thought

 

signification

 

sentences

 

combination

 
considers

Porphyry

 

represent

 

hekaston

 
sentence
 

Appendix

 
Aldrich
 
function
 

instructive

 

division

 
Mansel

bearing

 
misleading
 
qualification
 

purpose

 

predication

 

describe

 

semainei

 
ousian
 
keisthai
 

echein