FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84  
85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   >>   >|  
ssibilities, we _may_ conclude that one supposition is most probable _to us_. For this purpose it is not _necessary_ that specific experience or reason should have also proved the occurrence of each of the several events to be, as a fact, equally frequent. For, the probability of an event is not a quality of the event (since every event is in itself certain), but is merely a name for the degree of ground _we_ have, with our present evidence, for expecting it. Thus, if we know that a box contains red, white, and black balls, though we do not know in what proportions they are mingled, we have numerically appreciable grounds for considering the probability to be two to one against any one colour. Our judgment may indeed be said in this case to rest on the experience we have of the laws governing the frequency of occurrence of the different cases; but such experience is universal and axiomatic, and not specific experience about a particular event. Except, however, in games of chance, the purpose of which requires ignorance, such specific experience can generally be, and should be gained. And a slight improvement in the data profits more than the most elaborate application of the calculus of probabilities to the bare original data, e.g. to such data, when we are calculating the credibility of a witness, as the proportion, even if it could be verified, between the number of true and of erroneous statements a man, _qua_ man, may be supposed to make during his life. Before applying the Doctrine of Chance, therefore, we should lay a foundation for an evaluation of the chances by gaining positive knowledge of the facts. Hence, though not a _necessary_, yet a most usual condition for calculating the probability of a fact is, that we should possess a _specific_ knowledge of the proportion which the cases in which facts of the particular sort occur bear to the cases in which they do not occur. Inferences drawn correctly according to the Doctrine of Chances depend ultimately on causation. This is clearest, when, as sometimes, the probability of an event is deduced from the frequency of the occurrence of the causes. When its probability is calculated by merely counting and comparing the number of cases in which it has occurred with those in which it has not, the law, being arrived at by the Method of Agreement, is only empirical. But even when, as indeed generally, the numerical data are obtained in the latter way (since usually we c
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84  
85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

experience

 

probability

 

specific

 
occurrence
 

generally

 

purpose

 

Doctrine

 

proportion

 
calculating
 

number


frequency

 
knowledge
 

foundation

 
evaluation
 

gaining

 

chances

 

positive

 
statements
 

witness

 

erroneous


verified

 
supposed
 

applying

 

Chance

 

Before

 

clearest

 
arrived
 

occurred

 
calculated
 

counting


comparing

 

Method

 

Agreement

 

obtained

 
numerical
 
empirical
 
Inferences
 

correctly

 

condition

 

possess


Chances

 

depend

 
deduced
 

credibility

 

ultimately

 

causation

 
Except
 

expecting

 

evidence

 

present