FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104  
105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   >>  
efinite properties to be arrived at by abstraction, there are classes, viz. _kinds_, distinguished severally by an unknown multitude of independent properties (and about which classes therefore many assertions will be made), there must be a name for every _kind_. That is, besides a terminology, there must be a nomenclature, i.e. a collection of the names of all the lowest _kinds_, or _infimae species_. The Linnaean arrangements of plants and animals, and the French of chemistry, are nomenclatures. The peculiarity of a name which belongs to a nomenclature is, not that its meaning resides in its denotation instead of its connotation (for it resides in its connotation, like that of other concrete general names); but that, besides connoting certain attributes which its definition explains, it also connotes that these attributes are distinctive of a _kind_; and this fact its definition cannot explain. A philosophical language, then, must possess, first, precision, and next (the subject of the present chapter), completeness. Some have argued that, in addition, names are fitted for the purposes of thought in proportion as they approximate to mere symbols in compactness, through meaninglessness, and capability of use as counters without reference to the various objects which, though utterly different, they may thus at different times equally well represent. Such are, indeed, the qualities enabling us to employ the figures of arithmetic and the symbols of algebra perfectly mechanically according to general technical rules. But, in the first place, in our direct inductions, at all events, depending as they do on our perception of the particulars of the agreement and difference of the phenomena, we could never dispense with a distinct mental image of the latter. Further, even in deduction, though a syllogism is conclusive from its mere form, if the terms are unambiguous, yet the _practical_ validity of the reasoning depends on the hypothesis that no counteracting cause has interfered with the truth of the premisses. We can assure ourselves of this only by studying the phenomena at every step. For it is only in geometry and algebra that there is no danger from the Composition of Causes, or the superseding of one set of laws by another; and that, therefore, the propositions are categorically true. In sciences in general, then, the object should be, so far from keeping individualising peculiarities out of sight, to contrive the grea
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103   104  
105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   >>  



Top keywords:

general

 
phenomena
 

resides

 

connotation

 

symbols

 

definition

 

attributes

 

algebra

 

classes

 

properties


nomenclature

 

Further

 

deduction

 

syllogism

 

abstraction

 

distinct

 

mental

 

conclusive

 

dispense

 

unambiguous


arithmetic

 

distinguished

 

arrived

 

practical

 

events

 

depending

 

inductions

 

direct

 

technical

 

perception


particulars

 

perfectly

 
mechanically
 
validity
 

agreement

 

difference

 

hypothesis

 

categorically

 

sciences

 

propositions


object

 

contrive

 

peculiarities

 

individualising

 

keeping

 

superseding

 

Causes

 

interfered

 

premisses

 
depends