FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98  
99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   >>   >|  
esent in the imagination, is composed of an infinite number of parts. When we realize this, do we not free ourselves from the difficulties which seemed to make the motion of a point over a line an impossible absurdity? The line as revealed in a single experience either of sight or of touch is not composed of an infinite number of parts. It is composed of points seen or touched--least experiences of sight or touch, _minima sensibilia_. These are next to each other, and the point, in moving, takes them one by one. But such a single experience is not what we call a line. It is but one experience of a line. Though the experience is not infinitely divisible, the line may be. This only means that the visual or tactual point of the single experience may stand for, may represent, what is not a mere point but has parts, and is, hence, divisible. Who can set a limit to such possible substitutions? in other words, who can set a limit to the divisibility of a _real line_? It is only when we confuse the single experience with the real line that we fall into absurdities. What the mathematician tells us about real points and real lines has no bearing on the constitution of the single experience and its parts. Thus, when he tells us that between any two points on a line there are an infinite number of other points, he only means that we may expand the line indefinitely by the system of substitutions described above. We do this for ourselves within limits every time that we approach from a distance a line drawn on a blackboard. The mathematician has generalized our experience for us, and that is all he has done. We should try to get at his real meaning, and not quote him as supporting an absurdity. [1] "Seeing and Thinking," p. 149. CHAPTER VII OF TIME 27. TIME AS NECESSARY, INFINITE, AND INFINITELY DIVISIBLE.--Of course, we all know something about time; we know it as past, present, and future; we know it as divisible into parts, all of which are successive; we know that whatever happens must happen in time. Those who have thought a good deal about the matter are apt to tell us that time is a necessity of thought, we cannot but think it; that time is and must be infinite; and that it is infinitely divisible. These are the same statements that were made regarding space, and, as they have to be criticised in just the same way, it is not necessary to dwell upon them at great length. However, we must
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98  
99   100   101   102   103   104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

experience

 

single

 

divisible

 

points

 
infinite
 
composed
 

number

 

substitutions

 

infinitely

 

mathematician


thought

 

absurdity

 

length

 

CHAPTER

 

INFINITE

 

NECESSARY

 

statements

 
Seeing
 

However

 

meaning


Thinking
 
supporting
 

DIVISIBLE

 

successive

 

future

 

happen

 

criticised

 
present
 

necessity

 

INFINITELY


matter

 
absurdities
 

moving

 
minima
 

sensibilia

 

Though

 
represent
 
tactual
 

visual

 

experiences


difficulties

 

realize

 

imagination

 

motion

 

touched

 

revealed

 
impossible
 

system

 
indefinitely
 

expand