FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220  
221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   >>   >|  
ase with quantities of every kind, but only with those which are represented and apprehended by us as _extensive_."[3] [3] B. 203-4, M. 123. Kant opposes an extensive quantity to an intensive quantity or a quantity which has a degree. "That quantity which is apprehended only as unity and in which plurality can be represented only by approximation to negation = 0, I call _intensive quantity_."[4] The aspect of this ultimate distinction which underlies Kant's mode of stating it is that only an extensive quantity is a whole, i. e. something made up of parts. Thus a mile can be said to be made up of two half-miles, but a velocity of one foot per second, though comparable with a velocity of half a foot per second, cannot be said to be made up of two such velocities; it is essentially one and indivisible. Hence, from Kant's point of view, it follows that it is only an extensive magnitude which can, and indeed must, be apprehended through a successive synthesis of the parts. The proof of the axiom seems to be simply this: 'All phenomena as objects of perception are subject to the forms of perception, space and time. Space and time are [homogeneous manifolds, and therefore] extensive quantities, only to be apprehended by a successive synthesis of the parts. Hence phenomena, or objects of experience, must also be extensive quantities, to be similarly apprehended.' And Kant goes on to add that it is for this reason that geometry and pure mathematics generally apply to objects of experience. [4] B. 210, M. 127. We need only draw attention to three points. Firstly, no justification is given of the term 'axiom'. Secondly, the argument does not really appeal to the doctrine of the categories, but only to the character of space and time as forms of perception. Thirdly, it need not appeal to space and time as forms of perception in the proper sense of ways in which we apprehend objects, but only in the sense of ways in which objects are related[5]; in other words, it need not appeal to Kant's theory of knowledge. The conclusion follows simply from the nature of objects as spatially and temporally related, whether they are phenomena or not. It may be objected that Kant's thesis is that _all_ objects of perception are extensive quantities, and that unless space and time are allowed to be ways in which _we must perceive_ objects, we cannot say that all objects will be spatially and temporally related, and so extensive qu
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   196   197   198   199   200   201   202   203   204   205   206   207   208   209   210   211   212   213   214   215   216   217   218   219   220  
221   222   223   224   225   226   227   228   229   230   231   232   233   234   235   236   237   238   239   240   241   242   243   244   245   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

objects

 

extensive

 
quantity
 

perception

 
apprehended
 

quantities

 

phenomena

 

related

 

appeal

 

spatially


temporally

 
velocity
 

simply

 

experience

 
synthesis
 
successive
 
represented
 

intensive

 

Secondly

 
argument

doctrine
 

Thirdly

 

character

 

categories

 
generally
 
attention
 

justification

 

Firstly

 

points

 

proper


thesis
 

objected

 

allowed

 

perceive

 

apprehend

 

theory

 

knowledge

 

nature

 

conclusion

 
mathematics

aspect

 
ultimate
 
indivisible
 

essentially

 

magnitude

 
velocities
 

stating

 
comparable
 

distinction

 
underlies