FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   259   260   261   262   263   264   265   266   267   268   269   270   271   272   273   274   275   276   277   278   279   280   281   282   283  
284   285   286   287   288   289   290   291   292   293   294   295   296   297   298   299   300   301   302   303   304   305   306   307   308   >>   >|  
sh agriculture are distinguished, in settling their rotation, into white and green; the botanist divides the higher plants into gymnosperms and angiosperms, and the latter into monocotyledons and dicotyledons. The principle of resemblance and difference is recognised in all these cases; but what resemblances or differences are important depends upon the purpose to be served. Purposes are either ([alpha]) special or practical, as in gardening or hunting, or ([beta]) general or scientific, as in Botany or Zoology. The scientific purpose is merely knowledge; it may indeed subserve all particular or practical ends, but has no other end than knowledge directly in view. And whilst, even for knowledge, different classifications may be suitable for different lines of inquiry, in Botany and Zoology the Morphological Classification is that which gives the most general and comprehensive knowledge (see Huxley, _On the Classification of Animals_, ch. 1). Most of what a logician says about classification is applicable to the practical kind; but the scientific (often called 'Natural Classification'), as the most thorough and comprehensive, is what he keeps most constantly before him. Scientific classification comes late in human history, and at first works over earlier classifications which have been made by the growth of intelligence, of language, and of the practical arts. Even in the distinctions recognised by animals, may be traced the grounds of classification: a cat does not confound a dog with one of its own species, nor water with milk, nor cabbage with fish. But it is in the development of language that the progress of instinctive classification may best be seen. The use of general names implies the recognition of classes of things corresponding to them, which form their denotation, and whose resembling qualities, so far as recognised, form their connotation; and such names are of many degrees of generality. The use of abstract names shows that the objects classed have also been analysed, and that their resembling qualities have been recognised amidst diverse groups of qualities. Of the classes marked by popular language it is worth while to distinguish two sorts (_cf._ chap. xix. Sec. 4): Kinds, and those having but few points of agreement. But the popular classifications, made by language and the primitive arts, are very imperfect. They omit innumerable things which have not been found useful or noxious, or have bee
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   259   260   261   262   263   264   265   266   267   268   269   270   271   272   273   274   275   276   277   278   279   280   281   282   283  
284   285   286   287   288   289   290   291   292   293   294   295   296   297   298   299   300   301   302   303   304   305   306   307   308   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

recognised

 

classification

 
language
 

practical

 

knowledge

 
scientific
 

qualities

 

general

 

Classification

 

classifications


popular

 

Botany

 
Zoology
 

classes

 
things
 
resembling
 
comprehensive
 

purpose

 

implies

 

recognition


cabbage

 

confound

 
grounds
 

traced

 

distinctions

 

animals

 
development
 

progress

 

instinctive

 

species


objects

 

points

 

agreement

 

noxious

 

innumerable

 

primitive

 

imperfect

 
distinguish
 

degrees

 

generality


abstract

 

connotation

 
intelligence
 
classed
 

marked

 

groups

 

diverse

 
analysed
 

amidst

 

denotation