FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   2174   2175   2176   2177   2178   2179   2180   2181   2182   2183   2184   2185   2186   2187   2188   2189   2190   2191   2192   2193   2194   2195   2196   2197   2198  
2199   2200   2201   2202   2203   2204   2205   2206   2207   2208   2209   2210   2211   2212   2213   2214   2215   2216   2217   2218   2219   2220   2221   2222   2223   >>   >|  
ther. But in as far as a certain sort of pleasure is pursued as a principal aim, we can make of it, if not a specific character of a class properly so called, at least the principle and the tendency of a class in the works of art. Thus, for example, we could take the arts which, above all, satisfy the intelligence and imagination--consequently those which have as chief object the true, the perfect, and the beautiful--and unite them under the name of fine arts (arts of taste, arts of intelligence); those, on the other hand, which especially occupy the imagination and the reason, and which, in consequence, have for principal object the good, the sublime, and the touching, could be limited in a particular class under the denomination of touching arts (arts of sentiment, arts of the heart). Without doubt it is impossible to separate absolutely the touching from the beautiful, but the beautiful can perfectly subsist without the touching. Thus, although we are not authorized to base upon this difference of principle a rigorous classification of the liberal arts, it can at least serve to determine with more of precision the criterion, and prevent the confusion in which we are inevitably involved, when, drawing up laws of aesthetic things, we confound two absolutely different domains, as that of the touching and that of the beautiful. The touching and the sublime resemble in this point, that both one and the other produce a pleasure by a feeling at first of displeasure, and that consequently (pleasure proceeding from suitability, and displeasure from the contrary) they give us a feeling of suitability which presupposes an unsuitability. The feeling of the sublime is composed in part of the feeling of our feebleness, of our impotence to embrace an object; and, on the other side, of the feeling of our moral power--of this superior faculty which fears no obstacle, no limit, and which subdues spiritually that even to which our physical forces give way. The object of the sublime thwarts, then, our physical power; and this contrariety (impropriety) must necessarily excite a displeasure in us. But it is, at the same time, an occasion to recall to our conscience another faculty which is in us--a faculty which is even superior to the objects before which our imagination yields. In consequence, a sublime object, precisely because it thwarts the senses, is suitable with relation to reason, and it gives to us a joy by means of a higher
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   2174   2175   2176   2177   2178   2179   2180   2181   2182   2183   2184   2185   2186   2187   2188   2189   2190   2191   2192   2193   2194   2195   2196   2197   2198  
2199   2200   2201   2202   2203   2204   2205   2206   2207   2208   2209   2210   2211   2212   2213   2214   2215   2216   2217   2218   2219   2220   2221   2222   2223   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

touching

 

object

 

sublime

 

feeling

 

beautiful

 
imagination
 

faculty

 
pleasure
 

displeasure

 

suitability


physical

 

consequence

 

superior

 

reason

 

absolutely

 
thwarts
 
principle
 

intelligence

 
principal
 

contrary


suitable
 

unsuitability

 

composed

 
precisely
 

presupposes

 

proceeding

 

senses

 

resemble

 

higher

 

domains


produce

 

relation

 
impotence
 
excite
 

forces

 

subdues

 

spiritually

 

necessarily

 

impropriety

 

contrariety


confound

 

occasion

 

objects

 
embrace
 

yields

 

feebleness

 

obstacle

 
recall
 
conscience
 
perfect