FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103  
104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   >>   >|  
how _far away_ Mere delectation, meet for a minute's dream!"[B] [Footnote B: _Ibid._ 2089-2097.] So illimitably beyond his strength is such a life, that he finds himself like the drudging student who "Trims his lamp, Opens his Plutarch, puts him in the place Of Roman, Grecian; draws the patched gown close, Dreams, 'Thus should I fight, save or rule the world!'-- Then smilingly, contentedly, awakes To the old solitary nothingness."[A] [Footnote A: _The Ring and the Book_--_Giuseppe Caponsacchi_, 2098-2103.] The moral world with its illimitable horizon had Opened out around him, the voice of the new commandment bidding him "be perfect as his Father in heaven is perfect" had destroyed his peace, and made imperative a well nigh hopeless struggle; and, as he compares himself at his best with the new ideal, he breaks out into the cry, "O great, just, good God! Miserable Me!" This humility and contrition, this discontent verging on hopelessness, constituted, as we have seen, the characteristic attitude of Carlyle; and it represents a true and, in fact, an indispensable element of man's moral life. But this self-condemnation in the face of the moral law is nothing more than an element, and must not be taken either for the whole truth or for the most fundamental one. It is because it is taken as fundamental and final that the discrepancy between morality and religion is held to be absolute, and the consciousness of evil is turned against faith in the Good. It is an abstract way of thinking that makes us deduce, from the transcendent height of the moral ideal, the impossibility of attaining goodness, and the failure of God's purpose in man. And this is what Carlyle did. He stopped short at the consciousness of imperfection, and he made no attempt to account for it. He took it as a complete fact, and therefore drew a sharp line of distinction between the human and the divine. And, so far, he was right; for, if we look no further than this negative side, it is emphatically absurd to identify man, be he "philosopher" or not, with the Absolute. "Why callest thou Me good? there is none good save One, that is God." The "ought" _must_ stand above _all_ human attainment, and declare that "whatever is, is wrong." But whence comes the ought itself, the ideal which condemns us? Is it not also immanent in the fact it condemns? "Who is not acute enough," asks Hegel, "to see a grea
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   99   100   101   102   103  
104   105   106   107   108   109   110   111   112   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

consciousness

 

Footnote

 

perfect

 
condemns
 
element
 

fundamental

 

Carlyle

 

failure

 
goodness
 

attaining


impossibility
 

purpose

 

transcendent

 

height

 

religion

 

morality

 

discrepancy

 

absolute

 
abstract
 

thinking


turned

 

deduce

 

attainment

 

declare

 

callest

 

immanent

 

Absolute

 

distinction

 

complete

 

account


stopped

 

imperfection

 
attempt
 

divine

 

emphatically

 

absurd

 

identify

 
philosopher
 
negative
 

Dreams


patched

 
Grecian
 

solitary

 

nothingness

 
awakes
 
smilingly
 

contentedly

 

Plutarch

 

minute

 

delectation