FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139  
140   141   142   143   144   145   146   147   148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164   >>   >|  
between man and that massive drift of things which determines his destiny. Of the two terms of this relation, God signifies the latter, while freedom and immortality are prerogatives which religion bestows upon the former. Man, viewed from the stand-point of religion as an object of special interest to the universe, is said to have a soul; and by virtue of this soul he is said to be free and immortal, when thought of as having a life in certain senses independent of its immediate natural environment. The attempt to make this faith theoretically intelligible has led to the philosophical disciplines known as _theology_ and _psychology_.[199:14] [Sidenote: Theology Deals with the Nature and Proof of God.] Sect. 87. _Theology_, as a branch of philosophy, deals with _the proof and the nature of God_. Since "God" is not primarily a theoretical conception, the proof of God is not properly a philosophical problem. Historically, this task has been assumed as a legacy from Christian apologetics; and it has involved, at any rate so far as European philosophy is concerned, the definition of ultimate being in such spiritual terms as make possible the relation with man postulated in Christianity. For this it has been regarded as sufficient to ascribe to the world an underlying unity capable of bearing the predicates of perfection, omnipotence, and omniscience. Each proof of God has defined him pre-eminently in terms of some one of these his attributes. [Sidenote: The Ontological Proof of God.] Sect. 88. The _ontological_ proof of God held the foremost place in philosophy's contribution to Christianity up to the eighteenth century. This proof _infers the existence from the ideal_ of God, and so approaches the nature of God through the attribute of perfection. It owes the form in which it was accepted in the Middle Ages and Renaissance to St. Anselm, Archbishop of Canterbury at the close of the eleventh century. He argued from the idea of a most perfect being to its existence, on the ground that non-existence, or existence only in idea, would contradict its perfection. It is evident that the force of this argument depends upon the necessity of the idea of God. The argument was accepted in Scholastic Philosophy[201:15] largely because of the virtual acceptance of this necessity. Mediaeval thought was under the dominance of the philosophical ideas of Plato and Aristotle, and through them rationalism had come to be the unquestione
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   115   116   117   118   119   120   121   122   123   124   125   126   127   128   129   130   131   132   133   134   135   136   137   138   139  
140   141   142   143   144   145   146   147   148   149   150   151   152   153   154   155   156   157   158   159   160   161   162   163   164   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
existence
 

philosophical

 

philosophy

 
perfection
 

argument

 
thought
 

nature

 

century

 

relation

 

Christianity


Theology

 
Sidenote
 

necessity

 

accepted

 

religion

 

approaches

 

infers

 

eighteenth

 

Ontological

 
defined

omniscience

 

omnipotence

 
capable
 

bearing

 

predicates

 

eminently

 

foremost

 
contribution
 

ontological

 
attributes

largely

 

virtual

 

acceptance

 

depends

 
Scholastic
 

Philosophy

 

Mediaeval

 
rationalism
 

unquestione

 

Aristotle


dominance

 
evident
 

contradict

 

Anselm

 

Archbishop

 

Canterbury

 

underlying

 

Renaissance

 

Middle

 

eleventh