FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   825   826   827   828   829   830   831   832   833   834   835   836   837   838   839   840   841   842   843   844   845   846   847   848   849  
850   851   852   853   854   855   856   857   858   859   860   861   862   863   864   865   866   867   868   869   870   871   872   873   874   >>   >|  
er, no person can be under two opposite obligations. Yet sometimes the person who swears and the person to whom he swears have opposite intentions. Therefore an oath cannot always be binding. _On the contrary,_ It is written (Matt. 5:33): "Thou shalt perform thy oaths to the Lord." _I answer that,_ An obligation implies something to be done or omitted; so that apparently it regards neither the declaratory oath (which is about something present or past), nor such oaths as are about something to be effected by some other cause (as, for example, if one were to swear that it would rain tomorrow), but only such as are about things to be done by the person who swears. Now just as a declaratory oath, which is about the future or the present, should contain the truth, so too ought the oath which is about something to be done by us in the future. Yet there is a difference: since, in the oath that is about the past or present, this obligation affects, not the thing that already has been or is, but the action of the swearer, in the point of his swearing to what is or was already true; whereas, on the contrary, in the oath that is made about something to be done by us, the obligation falls on the thing guaranteed by oath. For a man is bound to make true what he has sworn, else his oath lacks truth. Now if this thing be such as not to be in his power, his oath is lacking in judgment of discretion: unless perchance what was possible when he swore become impossible to him through some mishap, as when a man swore to pay a sum of money, which is subsequently taken from him by force or theft. For then he would seem to be excused from fulfilling his oath, although he is bound to do what he can, as, in fact, we have already stated with regard to the obligation of a vow (Q. 88, A. 3, ad 2). If, on the other hand, it be something that he can do, but ought not to, either because it is essentially evil, or because it is a hindrance to a good, then his oath is lacking in justice: wherefore an oath must not be kept when it involves a sin or a hindrance to good. For in either case "its result is evil" [*Cf. Bede, Homil. xix, in Decoll. S. Joan. Bapt.] Accordingly we must conclude that whoever swears to do something is bound to do what he can for the fulfilment of truth; provided always that the other two accompanying conditions be present, namely, judgment and justice. Reply Obj. 1: It is not the same with a simple assertion, and wit
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   825   826   827   828   829   830   831   832   833   834   835   836   837   838   839   840   841   842   843   844   845   846   847   848   849  
850   851   852   853   854   855   856   857   858   859   860   861   862   863   864   865   866   867   868   869   870   871   872   873   874   >>   >|  



Top keywords:

person

 

present

 

obligation

 

swears

 

justice

 

hindrance

 

future

 
judgment
 
lacking
 
contrary

opposite

 

declaratory

 

obligations

 

essentially

 

subsequently

 

fulfilling

 

excused

 

regard

 
stated
 

intentions


wherefore

 

provided

 

accompanying

 
conditions
 

fulfilment

 

Accordingly

 

conclude

 

assertion

 
simple
 

involves


result

 

Decoll

 

impossible

 

answer

 
implies
 
difference
 

perform

 

affects

 

omitted

 

apparently


things

 

tomorrow

 

action

 

perchance

 
discretion
 

binding

 

mishap

 

Therefore

 
effected
 

swearing