FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   >>  
still possess the first essays in the grammatical science of the Brahmans, the so-called _pratisakhyas_. These works, though they merely profess to give rules on the proper pronunciation of the ancient dialect of the Vedas, furnish us at the same time with observations of a grammatical character, and particularly with those valuable lists of words, irregular or in any other way remarkable, the Ganas. These supplied that solid basis on which successive generations of scholars erected the astounding structure that reached its perfection in the grammar of Panini. There is no form, regular or irregular, in the whole Sanskrit language, which is not provided for in the grammar of Panini and his commentators. It is the perfection of a merely empirical analysis of language, unsurpassed, nay even unapproached, by anything in the grammatical literature of other nations. Yet of the real nature, and natural growth of language, it teaches us nothing. What then do we know of language after we have learnt the grammar of Greek or Sanskrit, or after we have transferred the network of classical grammar to our own tongue? We know certain forms of language which correspond to certain forms of thought. We know that the subject must assume the form of the nominative, the object that of the accusative. We know that the more remote object may be put in the dative, and that the predicate, in its most general form, may be rendered by the genitive. We are taught that whereas in English the genitive is marked by a final _s_, or by the preposition _of_, it is in Greek expressed by a final {~GREEK SMALL LETTER OMICRON~}{~GREEK SMALL LETTER FINAL SIGMA~}, in Latin by _is_. But what this {~GREEK SMALL LETTER OMICRON~}{~GREEK SMALL LETTER FINAL SIGMA~} and _is_ represent, why they should have the power of changing a nominative into a genitive, a subject into a predicate, remains a riddle. It is self-evident that each language, in order to be a language, must be able to distinguish the subject from the object, the nominative from the accusative. But how a mere change of termination should suffice to convey so material a distinction would seem almost incomprehensible. If we look for a moment beyond Greek and Latin, we see that there are in reality but few languages which have distinct forms for these two categories of thought. Even in Greek and Latin there is no outward distinction between the nominative and accusative of neuters. The Chinese language, i
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   70   71   72   73   74   75   76   >>  



Top keywords:

language

 
nominative
 

grammar

 

LETTER

 

grammatical

 

subject

 
object
 
genitive
 

accusative

 
Panini

irregular

 

perfection

 

OMICRON

 

thought

 

predicate

 

distinction

 

Sanskrit

 

general

 
dative
 

remote


rendered

 

taught

 

preposition

 

marked

 
English
 

expressed

 
remains
 

reality

 

languages

 
incomprehensible

moment

 

distinct

 

neuters

 

Chinese

 

outward

 

categories

 
riddle
 

evident

 

changing

 

represent


suffice

 

convey

 

material

 

termination

 
change
 
distinguish
 

valuable

 

character

 
observations
 

successive