FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   371   372   373   374   375   376   377   378   379   380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395  
396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   >>   >|  
g from pure principles, a hidden sensuous impulse may be involved. But he leaves unconsidered the possibility that, even when the inclinations are favorable to right action, the action may be performed, not from inclination, but because of the consciousness of duty. Given that a man is naturally industrious, does this happy predisposition protect him from fits of idleness? And if he resists them, must it always be his inclination to activity and never moral principle which overcomes the temptation? In yielding to the danger of confounding the limits of our certain knowledge of the purity of motives with the limits of moral action, and in admitting true morality only where action proceeds from principle in opposition to the inclinations, Kant really deserves the reproach of rigorism or exaggerated purism--sometimes groundlessly extended to the justifiable strictness of his views--and the ridicule of the well-known lines of Schiller ("Scruples of Conscience" and "Decision" at the conclusion of his distich-group "The Philosophers"): "The friends whom I love I gladly would serve, but to this inclination incites me; And so I am forced from virtue to swerve since my act, through affection, delights me. The friends whom thou lovest thou must first seek to scorn, for to no other way can I guide thee; 'Tis alone with disgust thou canst rightly perform the acts to which duty would lead thee." If we return from this necessary limitation of a groundless inference (that true morality is present only when duty is performed against our inclinations, when it is difficult for us, when a conflict with sensuous motives has preceded), to the development of the fundamental ethical conceptions, we find that important conclusions concerning the origin and content of the moral law result from the principle obtained by the analysis of moral judgment: this law commands with _unconditional authority_--for every rational being and under all circumstances--what has _unconditioned worth_--the disposition which corresponds to it. The universality and necessity (_unconditionalness_) of the categorical imperative proves that it springs from no other source than reason itself. Those who derive the moral law from the will of God subject it to a condition, viz., the immutability of the divine will. Those who find the source of moral legislation in the pursuit of happiness make rational will dependent on a natural law
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   371   372   373   374   375   376   377   378   379   380   381   382   383   384   385   386   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395  
396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
action
 

inclination

 
principle
 

inclinations

 
friends
 

morality

 

motives

 
limits
 

rational

 

source


performed
 

sensuous

 

limitation

 

groundless

 

return

 
natural
 

immutability

 
inference
 
present
 

preceded


development

 

conflict

 

difficult

 

happiness

 

disgust

 

dependent

 

rightly

 

divine

 

fundamental

 

legislation


perform
 

pursuit

 

condition

 
springs
 

circumstances

 

proves

 

disposition

 

corresponds

 
necessity
 
unconditionalness

imperative

 

unconditioned

 
categorical
 

authority

 

reason

 

origin

 

content

 

subject

 

conclusions

 

conceptions