FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409   410   411  
412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   433   434   435   436   >>   >|  
rableness of the beautiful rests on the fact that it establishes a pleasing harmony between the imagination and the understanding, hence between sensuous and intellectual apprehension, the aesthetic attitude is possible only in sensuous-rational beings. The agreeable exists for the animal as well, and the good is an object of approval for pure spirits; but the beautiful exists for humanity alone. Kant succeeded in giving very delicate and felicitous verbal expression to these distinctions: the agreeable gratifies _(vergnuegt)_ and excites inclination _(Neigung)_; the good is approved _(gebilligt)_ and arouses respect _(Achtung)_; the beautiful "pleases" _(gefaellt)_ and finds "favor" _(Gunst)_. In the progress of the investigation the principle that beauty depends on the form alone, and that the concept, the purpose, the nature of the object is not taken into account at all in aesthetic judgment, experiences limitation. In its full strictness this applies only to a definite and, in fact, a subordinate division of the beautiful, which Kant marks off under the name of pure or _free_ beauty. With this he contrasts _adherent_ beauty, as that which presupposes a generic concept to which its form must correspond and which it must adequately present. Too much a purist not to mark the coming in of an intellectual pleasure as a beclouding of the "purity" of the aesthetic satisfaction, he is still just enough to admit the higher worth of adherent beauty. For almost the whole of artificial beauty and a considerable part of natural beauty belong to this latter division, which we to-day term ideal and characteristic beauty. Examples of free or purely formal beauty are tapestry patterns, arabesques, fountains, flowers, and landscapes, the pleasurableness of which rests simply on the proportion of their form and relations, and not upon their conformity to a presupposed significance and determination of the thing. A building, on the contrary--a dwelling, a summer-house, a temple--is considered beautiful only when we perceive in it not merely harmonious relations of the parts one to another, but also an agreement between the form and the purpose or generic concept: a church must not look like a chalet. Here the external form is compared with an inner nature, and harmony is required between form and content. Adherent beauty is significant and expressive beauty, which, although the satisfaction in it is not "purely" aesthetic, neverthele
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   387   388   389   390   391   392   393   394   395   396   397   398   399   400   401   402   403   404   405   406   407   408   409   410   411  
412   413   414   415   416   417   418   419   420   421   422   423   424   425   426   427   428   429   430   431   432   433   434   435   436   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
beauty
 

beautiful

 
aesthetic
 

concept

 
purpose
 

purely

 

relations

 
satisfaction
 

generic

 

adherent


nature
 

division

 

harmony

 

agreeable

 

exists

 
sensuous
 

intellectual

 
object
 
tapestry
 

patterns


formal

 

Examples

 

flowers

 

simply

 

proportion

 

rableness

 

pleasurableness

 

landscapes

 

fountains

 

characteristic


arabesques
 

higher

 

artificial

 
considerable
 

establishes

 

belong

 

natural

 

determination

 
chalet
 
external

agreement

 

church

 
compared
 

expressive

 

neverthele

 

significant

 

Adherent

 

required

 

content

 

building