FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   324   325   326   327   328   329   330   331   332   333   334   335   336   337   338   339   340   341   342   343   344   345   346   347   348  
349   350   351   352   353   354   355   356   357   358   359   360   361   362   363   364   365   366   367   368   369   370   371   372   373   >>   >|  
priori_, though not as completed representations. They are functions, necessary actions of the soul, for the execution of which a stimulus from without, through sensations, is necessary, but which, when once this is given, the soul brings forth spontaneously. The external impulse merely gives the soul the occasion for such productive acts, while their grounds and laws are found in its own nature. In this sense Kant terms them "originally acquired," and in the Introduction to the _Critique of Pure Reason_ declares that although it is indubitable that "all our knowledge begins _with_ experience (impressions of sense), yet it does not all arise _from_ experience." That a representation or cognition is _a priori_[1] does not mean that it precedes experience in time, but that (apart from the merely exciting, non-productive stimulation through impressions already mentioned) it is independent of all experience, that it is not derived or borrowed from experience. [Footnote 1: The terms _a priori_ representation and pure representation (concept, intuition) are equivalent; but in judgments, on the other hand, there is a distinction. A judgment is _a priori_ when the connection takes place independently of experience, no matter whether the concepts connected are _a priori_ or not. If the former is the case the _a priori_ judgment is pure (mixed with nothing empirical); if the latter, it is mixed.] The material of intuition and thought is given to the soul, received by it; it arises through the action of objects upon the senses, and is always empirical. Intuition is the only organ of reality; in sensation the presence of a real object as the cause of the sensation is directly revealed. When Kant's transcendental idealism was placed by a reviewer on a level with the empirical idealism of Berkeley, which denies the existence of the external world, he distinctly asserted that it had never entered his mind to question the reality of external things. Further, after the existence of real things affecting the senses had been transformed in his mind from a basis of the investigation into an object of inquiry, he endeavored to defend this assumption (which at first he had naively borrowed from the realism of pre-scientific thought) by arguments, but without any satisfactory result.[1] [Footnote 1: The task of confirming the existence of things in themselves changes under his hands into another, that of proving the existence of external
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   324   325   326   327   328   329   330   331   332   333   334   335   336   337   338   339   340   341   342   343   344   345   346   347   348  
349   350   351   352   353   354   355   356   357   358   359   360   361   362   363   364   365   366   367   368   369   370   371   372   373   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
priori
 

experience

 
external
 

existence

 
empirical
 

representation

 

things

 
impressions
 

senses

 

reality


object
 

sensation

 

thought

 

Footnote

 

idealism

 
judgment
 

borrowed

 
intuition
 
productive
 

reviewer


asserted

 

actions

 

Berkeley

 

functions

 

transcendental

 

denies

 

distinctly

 

revealed

 

sensations

 

Intuition


objects
 

arises

 

action

 
directly
 

execution

 

stimulus

 

presence

 

representations

 
arguments
 
satisfactory

scientific

 

naively

 
realism
 

result

 

proving

 

confirming

 

affecting

 

Further

 

question

 

entered