FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72  
73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   >>   >|  
mentioned, Heft vii. of his _Untersuchungen zur deutschen Staats- und Rechtsgeschichte_, Breslau, 1880) to the Westphalian, Johannes Althusius (Althusen or Althaus) as a legal philosopher worthy of notice. He was born, 1557, in the Grafschaft Witgenstein; was a teacher of law in Herborn and Siegen from 1586, and Syndic in Emden from 1604 to his death in 1638. His chief legal work was the _Dicaeologica_, 1617 (a recasting of a treatise on Roman law which appeared in 1586), and his chief political work the _Politica_, 1603 (altered and enlarged 1610, and reprinted, in addition, three times before his death and thrice subsequently). Down to the beginning of the eighteenth century he was esteemed or opposed as chief among the _Monarchomachi_, so called by the Scotchman, Barclay (_De Regno et Regali Potestate_, 1600); since that time he has fallen into undeserved oblivion. The sovereign power (_majestas_) of the people is untransferable and indivisible, the authority vested in the chosen wielder of the administrative power is revocable, and the king is merely the chief functionary; individuals are subjects, it is true, but the community retains its sovereignty and has its rights represented over against the chief magistrate by a college of ephors. If the prince violates the compact, the ephors are authorized and bound to depose the tyrant, and to banish or execute him. There is but one normal state-form; monarchy and polyarchy are mere differences in administrative forms. Mention should finally be made of his valuation of the social groups which mediate between the individual and the state: the body politic is based on the narrower associations of the family, the corporation, the commune, and the province. While with Bodin the historical, and with Gentilis the _a priori_ method of treatment predominates, Hugo Grotius[1] combines both standpoints. He bases his system on the traditional distinction of two kinds of law. The origin of positive law is historical, by voluntary enactment; natural law is rooted in the nature of man, is eternal, unchangeable, and everywhere the same. He begins by distinguishing with Gentilis the _jus humanum_ from the _jus divinum_ given in the Scriptures. The former determines, on the one hand, the legal relations of individuals, and, on the other, those of whole nations; it is _jus personale_ and _jus gentium_.[2] [Footnote 1: Hugo de Groot lived 1583-1645. He was born in Delft, became Fiscal of H
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   48   49   50   51   52   53   54   55   56   57   58   59   60   61   62   63   64   65   66   67   68   69   70   71   72  
73   74   75   76   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   85   86   87   88   89   90   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
administrative
 
historical
 
Gentilis
 
ephors
 

individuals

 

corporation

 

commune

 

province

 

family

 

associations


individual

 

politic

 

narrower

 

deutschen

 

predominates

 

Grotius

 

treatment

 
method
 
Untersuchungen
 

priori


mediate

 

normal

 
Staats
 

monarchy

 

tyrant

 

banish

 
execute
 

polyarchy

 

valuation

 
social

groups

 
finally
 

differences

 

Mention

 
combines
 

standpoints

 

nations

 

personale

 

relations

 

Scriptures


determines

 
gentium
 
Fiscal
 

Footnote

 

divinum

 

humanum

 

origin

 

positive

 

voluntary

 
distinction