FREE BOOKS

Author's List




PREV.   NEXT  
|<   537   538   539   540   541   542   543   544   545   546   547   548   549   550   551   552   553   554   555   556   557   558   559   560   561  
562   563   564   565   566   567   568   569   570   571   572   573   574   575   576   577   578   579   580   581   582   583   584   585   586   >>   >|  
usation." When the phenomena are complex the deductive method must be called in to aid: from the inductively ascertained laws of the action of single causes this deduces the laws of their combined action; and, as a final step, the results of such ratiocination are verified by the proof of their agreement with empirical facts. To explain a phenomenon means to point out its cause; the explanation of a law is its reduction to other, more general laws. In all this, however, we remain within the sphere of phenomena; the essence of nature always eludes our knowledge. In the chapter "Of Liberty and Necessity" (book vi. chap, ii.) Mill emphasizes the position that the necessity to which human actions are subject must not be conceived, as is commonly done, as irresistible compulsion, for it denotes nothing more than the uniform order of our actions and the possibility of predicting them. This does not destroy the element in the idea of freedom which is legitimate and practically valuable: we have the power to alter our character; it is formed _by_ us as well as _for_ us; the desire to mould it is one of the most influential circumstances in its formation. The principle of morality is the promotion of the happiness of all sentient beings. Mill differs from Bentham, however, from whom he derives the principle of utility, in several important particulars--by his recognition of qualitative as well as of quantitative differences in pleasures, of the value of the ordinary rules of morality as intermediate principles, of the social feelings, and of the disinterested love of virtue. Opponents of the utilitarian theory have not been slow in availing themselves of the opportunities for attack thus afforded.[1] A third distinguished representative of the same general movement is Alexander Bain, the psychologist (born 1818; _The Senses and the Intellect_, 3d ed., 1868; _The Emotions and the Will_, 3d ed., 1875; _Mental and Moral Science_, 1868, 3d ed., 1872, part ii., 1872; _Mind and Body_, 3d ed., 1874). [Footnote 1: On the relation of Bentham and Mill cf. Hoeffding, p. 68: Sidgwick's _Outlines_, chap. iv. Sec. 16; and John Grote's _Examination of the Utilitarian Philosophy_, 1870, chap. i.] The system projected by Herbert Spencer (born 1820), the major part of which has already appeared, falls into five parts: _First Principles_, 1862, 7th ed., 1889; _Principles of Biology_, 1864-67, 4th ed., 1888; _Principles of Psychology_, 1855, 5
PREV.   NEXT  
|<   537   538   539   540   541   542   543   544   545   546   547   548   549   550   551   552   553   554   555   556   557   558   559   560   561  
562   563   564   565   566   567   568   569   570   571   572   573   574   575   576   577   578   579   580   581   582   583   584   585   586   >>   >|  



Top keywords:
Principles
 

actions

 

general

 

Bentham

 

action

 

principle

 
morality
 
phenomena
 

Senses

 
principles

Alexander

 

psychologist

 
intermediate
 

quantitative

 

qualitative

 

recognition

 

differences

 

pleasures

 
movement
 
ordinary

Intellect

 

distinguished

 
opportunities
 
utilitarian
 

Opponents

 

attack

 

availing

 
theory
 

Emotions

 

virtue


representative

 

social

 

feelings

 

afforded

 
disinterested
 

relation

 
appeared
 

projected

 
system
 

Herbert


Spencer

 

Psychology

 

Biology

 
Footnote
 

Mental

 

Science

 

Hoeffding

 

Examination

 

Utilitarian

 
Philosophy